I suspect that there’s more here that we can agree on than might initially appear.
I agree. I am all for cooperation, division of labour and shared communities.
My only requirement is that all such cooperation be done on a voluntary basis.
In order to make your case at all, you’d have to assume a certain sort of social order already: likely some sort of anarcho-capitalism? Yet, even this sort of approach assumes that those in it are willing to take on the sorts of values and ideas of anarcho-capitalism. As of yet, we have no good reason for thinking this.
The ideal I am advocating is a society in which all interactions are voluntary, and (which is equivalent) force may never be legitimately initiated against another person or their peaceful projects.
How people choose to interact within this peaceful framework is, to me, of secondary importance.
Maybe they are able and maybe they’re not.
...
Nor, even under an anarcho-capitalist social order would this follow.
Nor, even under social democracy or socialism.
In general, any solution requires three ingredients:
1. Knowledge (of the problem and effective ways of solving it)
2. Will (desire to work towards a solution)
3. Means (effective resources required to affect a solution)
Governments offer no advantage over peaceful cooperation on any of those three:
1. Knowledge of the problem is typically better available to local, small-scale operators; government decision-makers sitting in a remote capital lack specific knowledge required to design an effective, tailored and appropriate solution
2. Democratic governments reflect, at best, the will of the people. If a democratic government wishes to solve a problem, that is a reflection that a majority of people want it solved. However, just because a democratic government doesn't desire to solve a particular problem doesn't mean that there aren't enough people (albeit a minority) who wish it solved.
3. Government doesn't produce resources. At best, it efficiently moves them from one set of hands to another. In practice, much waste is involved in the process. If a society has the means to solve a problem through government mediation, it obviously has the means to do so without government interference.
So what? Both on the Left and Right agree that political parties pander to their respective groups while deceiving the general public as to their genuine interests. How some political group or party makes use of a term is irrelevant as to the reality status of what the term represents.
I am in neither the left nor the right. I am not calling for a right government. I am calling for no government.
It may be—or it may not be!
It must be. The majority (for instance) doesn't define anything. The majority doesn't act. Only individuals act. There may well be a "good" over which a majority of people agree. But that doesn't make it a "public good". Merely a "popular good".
By the way, whether such things require ‘independence’ of thought and decision making is irrelevant to whether or not groups of people can collectively value the same sorts of things.
Again, groups of people don't value things. Only individuals value things. There may well be a group of people who, each individually, value the same thing. But that doesn't make it a group valuation.
To be clear, I fully recognise that people's valuations are very much dependent on their social context, including interactions with others. But ultimately, the valuation is
always individual.
On the more broad ontological argument, you haven’t yet established why the”individual” isn’t an equally confusing conventional reality. To make your case work in the end, it would seem reasonable to first show what is meant by such a thing and how it, then, ought to be equally fundamental to political theory.
I am not sure I understand your point here. In reality, individuals act, make decisions, value things (as demonstrated through their actions), etc.
Groups do none of those things, accept through a verbal slight of hand whereby a decision supported by a majority becomes a group decision.
The “wage,” for example, is not a cooperative element in the wealth-producing order not just because it denies choices to the laborer, but because it is a necessary element for a socially created system to continue to benefit others who do not create the market worth of that labor.
This seems like an important point. A wage doesn't deny workers choices - it adds one more choice (namely to accept the terms of an offer of employment) to whatever set of choices they already had.
In the context of a voluntaryist society (i.e. one based exclusively on voluntary interactions), wage relations signify a choice for distributing the value created by a joint enterprise whereby one or more of the parties ("workers") receive a constant amount, regardless (and temporally ahead of) actual revenues, while other parties (business owners which may, but need not, also own the capital) receive the residual value (which may be a profit or a loss, i.e. a negative amount).
It is obvious that business owners do participate in creating the market worth of the labour. If they didn't, the labourers would have no reason to agree to the agreement - they would simply create the value of their own, and keep it in its entirety.
Business owners typically contribute in a number of critical ways:
1. Advancing wages to workers who are unwilling or unable to wait until the product is actually produced and sold
2. Insulating workers from short-term uncertainty and fluctuation in the value produced by the enterprise
3. Possessing the entrepreneurial alertness required to identify useful, profitable, valuable modes of production
4. Using their savings to acquire the capital equipment required for an efficient production
5. Providing managerial services for the running of the business
6. Providing professional expertise, guiding and directing less-experienced workers
7. Using their reputation to assure customers of the quality of their products
Again, absent artificial barriers created by government regulations, any worker or group of workers who believe that the owners of the business are keeping for themselves an unfair share of the value produced by the business are always at liberty to leave their employer and create their own business, while, as necessary, hiring those ingredients provided by the owner.
For example, workers can, in lieu of using capital equipment purchased and provided by the employer, opt to take a bank loan with which to fund the initial purchase of capital equipment. This isn't a theoretical proposition - it is a daily occurrence.
The issue is that the capitalist argues that he has right to the market value of your labor.
Not at all. At most, the capitalist argues that he has the right to whatever you and he agreed for
in advance. Thus if I agreed to work for X hours in exchange for $Y and nothing more, my capitalist employer has the right to retain whatever excess value remains after my wages (and other expenses) have been paid (
if any value remains).
The capitalist doesn't argue for any right not explicitly, knowingly and voluntarily agreed-to by the worker!
There’s nothing that capitalists DO to earn that right!
I listed at least seven different things capitalists typically do to "earn that right".
The bottom line is simple. If the capitalists do not contribute anything of value,
why do workers agree to work for them, rather than for themselves?Here is another way of looking at it. One of the most valued "things" in the context of the economy is "jobs". What is a "job"? It is precisely what the capitalist (or socialist) employer brings to the table. A "job" involves all those ingredients (listed above) that are required before the mere labour of a worker has any value within society.
The value of everything capitalists bring to the table is reflected in the huge value members of society (from common workers to heads of state) place on "jobs".
For socialism, the economic order and the governmental order are owned by the people-NOT THE PUBLIC OR THE MARKET!
The "market" is nothing other than the collection of choices made by people. The "public" is another word for the people.
The market, in fact, is the only true expression of the will of the people. True, because it doesn't go through the distorting lens of politicians and other government decision-makers.
But there’s not only NO guarantee of this under Libertarianism-but the opposite is far likelier, just as history has shown.
What historic episode do you have in mind that showed the opposite?
So, while I’m free to pursue the means necessary to fulfil my needs and desires, I MUST do so within the narrow limits of what other people own and what they may rightly deny me.
Indeed. But I must stress (something I rarely do often enough) that the only property worthy of protection is
justly-acquired property, rather than arbitrary titles awarded by government.
For a resource to become a person's justly-acquired property, that acquisition has to proceed without the initiation of force. Essentially, there are only two ways that can happen:
1. A
previously-unused resource is incorporated into a person's projects in such a ways as to reasonably require the exclusion of others. Note that by acquiring the resource, no other person is harmed, as the resource, by definition, wasn't used. If a resource was used, but not owned, any property rights acquired are limited by the need to respect the pre-existing use pattern.
2. A resource already owned by another person is transferred voluntarily. This could be as a gift (e.g. parent to child, or charitable assistance), as an exchange (e.g. barter, monetary sale) or conditional upon performance of a task (e.g. wage labour, payment for services rendered)
With that in mind, any attempt by you to violate my property rights is equivalent to your initiation of force against me or my peaceful projects. Under normal conditions (i.e. excluding life-threatening emergencies, or "life boat" situations of severely-scarce essential resources), such initiation of force would be (by the moral code I am advancing) illegitimate.
My means are equal to what I have, including my abilities.
Plus whatever other people
willingly give you.
Those with no property and little ability will have no liberty or even potential to gain it.
Everybody owns, at the very least, their own body. Those with no external property nor the ability to provide others with useful services would, indeed, have to rely on the contribution of others.
This tends to be the case under all social systems. The only difference is whether your system sanctions the initiation of force against peaceful people to
force them to help third parties, or whether help may only be asked for, rather than demanded at the point of a gun.
Btw, certain terms (including "liberty", "freedom", "exploitation", "coercion", "violence", "fairness") are, in the context of discussions such as the one we are conducting, so broad as to be virtually useless.
Eventually, those who can and have a mind and interest in gobbling up as much of the economic resources as possible, along with the available labor resources at some specific economic time, over the many who have utterly NO interest in market matters whatsoever- would own the bulk of the “social” order (since, quite logically, the social order is structured in just the economic way you support).
You are making the implicit (and wrong) assumption that the relevant quantity of "economic resources" is limited. In fact, people acquire property by increasing the amount (measured by value) of economic resources available to society.
When an unused is brought into use (homesteading), its value is added to the value of economic resources available in society.
When an exchange takes place (whether of one good for another, one good for money, a good for service or money for service), both sides to the exchange engage in it only following their subjective assessment of that which they receive as having greater value (to them) than that which they give up. In other words, economic value is created in each voluntary exchange.
Thus the image of "gobbling up economic resources" is misleading. In fact, people create value through their productive efforts. They normally retain a fraction of the value they create, while passing much of that value to other members in society.
Consider, for example, a profitable company. Some people focus on the profit "extracted" by its owners. But much more important than that profit is the value added to every single party with which the company interacts - suppliers, workers and customers. Each of them is enriched by that interaction (for otherwise, they wouldn't choose to engage in it). In aggregate, the value to society far exceeds any profit retained by corporate owners.
With that in mind, it is clear that in a voluntarist society there are no "winners" and "losers". Rather, everybody wins from a large number of positive-sum exchanges and productive activities. Sure - some people may become very wealthy. But invariably, they become wealthy by making many others better off.
When the social-natural order is divvied up by capitalist-market forces, some will have more-others simply will have none.
In fact, under capitalist market forces, the lowest members of society benefit the most. To wit, members of the upper class have lived comfortable lives in every age. But while pre-capitalist working class people existed on the verge of starvation, rarely being able to afford even the most modest luxuries, capitalist working class people routinely enjoy the kinds of luxuries that nobody could even dream of a few decades ago. Most so-called "poor" families in America, for example, own cars, live in spacious and air-conditioned homes, own multiple colour TVs, refrigerators, microwaves, washer/driers, gaming systems, cellular phones, and on and on. They have access to a wider range of food products than did the kings of the middle ages. Not to mention their ability to travel, communicate and acquire knowledge.
If, for example, I’m extremely successful over my market-geographical domain, I’ll likely not take kindly to some innovative capitalist who would appear to start eating away at my market. If I could form some legal-solution or council or whatever non-market means to stop him, it would be in my interest to do so. Moreover, I would have even greater reason to do so if I had, for whatever reason, the support of the people.
This is why social/political norms are so crucially important. In today's US, for example, no person, no matter how wealthy, popular or politically powerful, can, with impunity, disobey a decision of the US Supreme Court. If a popular President tried to do that, he wouldn't remain either popular or president for long.
I am calling for a society in which respect for other people's property rights occupies the same role in people's scale of norms as respect for the Constitution does in today's America.
Within such a society, an extremely successful capitalist would no more be able to use legal solutions to stop an innovative competitors than the President of the US can avoid handing over power after an electoral defeat. The public won't stand for it. Period.
After all, if the only rule is respect of others property, and I find that my place of work is moving abroad, I might be encouraged to find work elsewhere-or I might simply see it within my immediate interests to organize politically and FORCE the plant or whatever-to stay.
Again, no more so than workers can (with impunity) steal their employer's property. Note that such an effort by workers is futile. The workers can physically take over the production plant, but not, typically, pay suppliers (or themselves). Nor, if the plant is losing money, expect to retain their jobs for long.
You’ve nowhere explained what private property is and how something is “justly acquired,” let alone why we ought to have these things.
I have now done so above. Fundamentally, private property is the formalisation of the Non Aggression Principle, formulated as
"It is wrong to initiate force against another person or their peaceful ongoing projects". It is, in other words, nothing more or less than the intuitive moral calling that using force against peaceful others is wrong.
The point is that both the politician and the capitalist have shared reasons for mixing their respective domains: the interests of both, in a capitalist system, are often one and the same-often by one and the same group.
Indeed. Just as the politician and the religious leader had shared reasons for mixing their respective domains. But that shared interest isn't enough to overcome deeply-rooted and broadly-held societal norms, such as the one which, in contemporary western culture, abhor involvement of government in matters of faith.
Similarly, once the NAP (perhaps in a slightly weaker form that still allows a minimalist "law-and-order" government, as some of my non-anarchist libertarians friends prefer) is similarly well-established, the shared interests of the politician and the capitalist will be insufficient to affect government intervention in economic matters.
Religion and religious ideas MAY involve power systems, or they may not. Political systems cannot do without economic systems
I honestly don't see why. In fact, from the vantage point of the 16th century, for example, the mutual involvement of religious ideas and power systems would seem much more inevitable than that of political systems and economics.
Also, it was the LAW, see our Constitution, that made religion a personal matter,i.e., FORCED religion to a secondary optional -personal issue.
The American system happens to be based on a written Constitution. But norms against government imposition of religious values are equally strong in Britain, where they aren't enshrined in any law or written document. In principle, Parliament
could pass a law that prohibits non-Christian faiths from practising. In practice, such move is unthinkable in today's Britain (though it was obviously commonplace in the 16th century).
As for the Constitution, it is, again, social norms rather than written words that dictate the effective limitations it places on government. While social norms in America are fairly strict regarding the separation of Church and State, prohibition against freedom of speech, for example, is much weaker, allowing gaping exceptions to the simple rule "Congress shall make no law...".
The enumerated powers doctrine is even more obviously abused.
So you see, it isn't a
written law, but only "law" in its most general sense of "widely accepted and legitimately enforceable norms" that effectively limits government's scope of legitimate action.
As a side note, if I were you I would become much more familiar with how religion and its ideas have and are currently influencing U.S. policy both Federally and at the state-level. Just this past week N.C. was trying to pass a law establishing a state religion. The debate on this issue is far from settled. The law and the courts are still attempting to clarify this very amendment.
There is backwards-and-forwards around the edges of the envelope of legitimate government actions. But there is no doubt that those edges are very far from where they have been in, say, 16th century England.
I can see a libertarian (obviously non-anarchist) government in which, for example, the use of taxation to fund overseas pre-emptive military strikes is an issue at the edge of what would be considered legitimate government action, but in which protective tariffs, eminent domain confiscation, drug laws, labour regulations, tax-funded social welfare programs and the thousands of other things governments do today would be considered illegitimate by virtually all members of society.
When owners decide to move, include some new labor-saving technology, or simply merge with another making competition more difficult, this directly impacts us objectively and in ways that don’t necessarily add diversity to the market.
Our normal, everyday moral intuition requires much more than "object impact" before the use of force is considered legitimate. When a girl I fancy prefers another man, I am "objectively" impacted in ways that, for me, may be very important. Yet nobody believes that such an impact legitimises my assaulting that man.
Rather than the vague term of "objectively impact", we use a much more specific term to identify what interests I may legitimately (myself or through delegation to others) protect using force. We call it "property".
So, you do support coercion to protect a person and his property?
I do support the use of force (I wouldn't call it "coercion", but note that "coercion" is one of those vague terms I dislike using) to protect a person and his (justly-acquired) property.
I support a system whereby institutions do exist to protect people's property rights (including rights in their own body, contractual rights, prohibition of fraud, etc.), but in which those institutions are both (1) voluntarily funded (i.e. not through taxes), and (2) do not enjoy a territorial monopoly (i.e. more than one may operate concurrently).
As already pointed out, I see no reason why worker and capitalist alike would want the Libertarian view at all when there’s far more to be gained by both by NOT having such a so-called anarchic order.
It is in virtually everybody's (rightly-understood, long-term) interests to maintain law and order. It is (less obviously, but still very much so, in my view) in virtually everybody's (rightly-understood, long-term) interests to respect the NAP (and, by consequence, other people's property).
Once that is understood by most members in society, the rest follows. In precisely the same way that virtually everybody today understands that judicial decisions ought to be respected.
Once norms associated with law and order, security and long-term growth are well-established, members of society reject opportunistic (and criminal) attempts to violate those norms. Human nature is such that it rebels against such attempts even if those attempts do not immediately endanger our selfish interests.
Whatever the amount or the identity of the objects involved in the means of production and owners of production may be at any given time- there are, nonetheless, distinct relationships between these market players.
My point isn't that the nature of the means of production changes over time. We both agree on that. My point, rather, is that at any given time in history, the pool of available means of production isn't fixed. Rather, means of production are routinely and regularly created (and destroyed). Thus, they aren't subject to monopolization. This is an important point. Because means of production are readily created, workers who choose to engage in a mutually-beneficial arrangement with owners of such means of production do so because they assess that it is better for them to give up some of the surplus value created by their labour in exchange for the convenience of using the means of production provided by others.
In effect, the participants in the productive enterprise each bring something to the table, and each take something away. There is a (multi-party) exchange going on. The terms of the exchange are mutually agreed by all.
Workers "give up" some of the surplus value in exchange for using means of production (in a very broad sense, often dominated by non-material assets such as reputation, innovation, etc.). Business owners "give up" some of the surplus value in exchange for the labour of the workers. More and more often, the lines are blurred through stock options, production-related bonuses, part-ownership, etc.
What arguments do you have to show that labor had or made some sort of choice to work for capitalists?
Very simply, nobody held a gun to their head. They chose (often eagerly) to work for the capitalists. In fact, the vast majority of today's capitalists (by which I take it you really mean some combination of business owners and senior managers) haven't been born capitalist. They started their career as workers, and, through ability, hard work, entrepreneurship, prudence and talent, made their way to their current position.
The exact same road is open to all workers.
In a society which doesn't accept parasitism as a way of life, every able person has to produce in order to acquire the necessities of life. Capitalists offer workers a much better opportunity to produce than would otherwise be available to them (see my point above about "jobs" and their real and perceived value).
Does capitalism justify itself by voluntary agreement or by just acquisition? If just acquisition is, or can be, the same as ‘nothing but voluntary economic-social arrangements,’ then you cannot mean that capitalism is about one keeping or earning what one produces!
Capitalism is, first and foremost, about voluntary relations. In practice, however, voluntary relations tend to lead to each person retaining the value they produce. This is an "asymptotic" relation. In other words, the operations of the market tend to push wages and prices in that direction. However, at any given moment, the relation need not hold exactly.
I can unfold for you the rather long story of how capitalists have spent a whole history in order to set labor policy, tell tales of literal bloodshed that labor had to fight in order to get basic rights to negotiate, and of many-many stories of union busting and threats made against labor for even daring to collectively discuss possibilities of bringing in democratic principles to the workplace.
None of which would be relevant to the question I asked. If the workers rejected the capitalist offer of employment and just started their own company, the issue of labour union would be moot.
Why didn't they?
Socialists have little problem explaining why many laborers in an economic tradition that has dominated and structured their culture for more than three-hundred years would “choose” a capitalist arrangement over some alternative. Our law, social organizations, many of our churches, key teachers, a major political party and its many advocates all support and speak out for it. To pretend that such labor decisions are made in some sort of voluntaristic vacuum is just that: pretending!
In both Britain and the US (and, as far as I know, many other places), norms valuing entrepreneurship, becoming "self-made man", as well as mutual aid and collaboration amongst workers are equally present.
In today's age of start-ups and IPOs you have to be a hermit not to realise that starting your own business (alone or with a group of others) is not just socially acceptable, it is highly valued and rewarded.
Yet most workers (and I personally amongst them) prefer (for understandable prudential reasons) the convenience and security of wage employment over the hard work and risks associated with self-production.
Or, rather the range of value that a society of consumers, educated labor, and capital investment freely provided to the employer.
But since employers (with the exception of crony capitalists which, as you know, I completely reject) don't belong to a legally-privileged class, whatever value a society of consumers, educated labour and capital investments are freely provided to the employer, they would be equally provided to any of his workers. Such background conditions for success still do not explain why it is that most people prefer wage employment over self-start.
Since the largest and most successful businesses rely heavily on government subsidies and bailouts due to bad-short-sighted economic interests, I fail to see “market know how” here.
I agree. Government subsidies and bailouts (as well as less obvious assistance through regulation and tariffs) do tend to bias the playing field against workers. You and I can join in calling for their abolition.
I never claimed that workers get a fair deal in today's world. Rather, I claim that they would get a fair deal in a world in which government doesn't get involved in the economy, and, therefore, government subsidies and bailouts wouldn't exist.
I'll stop here for lack of time. There is plenty more to discuss!
Free men are not equal and equal men are not free.
Government is not the solution. Government is the problem.